User:Oceanflynn/sandbox/Moral anger

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Moral anger

Philosophical perspectives[edit]

Ancient history[edit]

Aristotle writes about anger in 350 BC in Chapter II of Rhetoric, saying that, "Anger may be defined as an impulse, accompanied by pain, to a conspicuous revenge for a conspicuous slight directed without justification towards what concerns oneself or towards what concerns one's friends. If this is a proper definition of anger, it must always be felt towards some particular individual, e.g. Cleon, and not 'man' in general. It must be felt because the other has done or intended to do something to him or one of his friends. It must always be attended by a certain pleasure-that which arises from the expectation of revenge. For since nobody aims at what he thinks he cannot attain, the angry man is aiming at what he can attain, and the belief that you will attain your aim is pleasant."[1]. According to the 1995 article by Simon Kemp and K. T. Strongman published in the The American Journal of Psychology, Aristotle said "that anger, which arises from perceived injustice, is useful for preventing injustice, and that the opposite of anger is a kind of insensibility."[2]: 398 

According to Kristján Kristjánsson's 2005 article in the Journal of Philosophy of Education, Aristotle said that "what we should be aiming at in anger regulation is...neither the eradication of anger nor its control through calculated self-discipline but rather learning to experience that emotion…as part of our true selves in an uninhibited, rational and morally fitting way."[3]: 681 

In his 2002 Ratio article entitled "Aristotle's Account of Anger: Narcissism and Illusions of Self-Sufficiency", Stephen Leighton said that Aristotle defined anger as "desire, accompanied by pain, for conspicuous revenge because of a conspicuous slight that was directed, without justification, against oneself or those near to one."[4]: 26  Leighton says that Aristotle valued anger as part of a "virtuous and flourishing life".[4]

Moral anger and social psychology[edit]

In their 1993 article in the Journal of Personality and Social Psychology Haidt, Koller, and Dias found strong support for the social intuitionism model of moral judgment used in moral psychology.[5]

Moral emotions, in general, are "those emotions that are linked to the interests or welfare either of society as a whole or at least of persons other than the judge or agent."[6]: 853 

In their 1999 article, Dacher Keltner and Jonathan Haidt said that anger—when it was not a "lingering trait"—was more "moral than immoral",[7] according to a 2016 Organization Studies article by Dirk Lindebaum and Gabriel Yiannis.[8] Keltner, Haidt, and by extension Keltner and Lindebaum say that "[s]ocial functional accounts define emotions, and especially anger, in terms of consequences of goal‐directed behaviors,[7] which would mean that a "function and a consequence of anger" is to "redress[...] injustice.[8]

In 2000, Haidt, Bjorklund, and Murphy undertook the original moral dumbfounding study, "Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds no reason",Cite error: The <ref> tag has too many names (see the help page). which was later replicated in four studies in 2017 by the research team which included Cillian McHugh, Marek McGann, Eric R. Igou, and Elaine L. Kinsella.[9] They noticed a behavioral pattern that called "moral dumbfounding," in which "the stubborn and puzzled maintenance of a moral judgment without supporting reasons" persists.Cite error: The <ref> tag has too many names (see the help page).: 6 

In their 2001 Journal of Applied Social Psychology article, "Sexual morality: The cultures and emotions of conservatives and liberals", Haidt and Matthew Hersh ...[10]

In Jonathan Haidt's oft-cited 2001 article "The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment", published in Psychological Review, he describes how moral judgement can be "plagued by two illusions"—the wag-the-dog illusion and the "allusion of objectivity."[11] In the former, he described how if we "believe that our own moral judgment (the dog) is driven by our own moral reasoning (the tail)". The "allusion of objectivity, refers to the way in which we expect the "successful rebuttal of an opponent's arguments to change the opponent's mind" in a "moral argument." He compared this to the belief that "forcing a dog's tail to wag by moving it with your hand will make the dog happy. The wag-the-dog illusion follows directly from the mechanics of the reasoning process described above." Haidt said that one of the mechanisms underlying naive realism in which "people think that they see the world as it is whereas their opponents in a moral dispute are biased by ideology and self-interest."[6]: 852–870  In "The emotional dog and its rational tail", Haidt said that anger is likely the "most underappreciated moral emotion."[6]: 856 

From Haidt's The Righteous Mind

In his 2012 publication, Haidt says that humans have "five basic moral receptors: those pertaining to caring, fairness, loyalty, authority and sanctity[/purity]." Haidt and his co-researcher Sean Stevens, at the Leonard N. Stern School of Business, conducted a survey on their website called yourmorals.org, with which users could be rated on these moral receptors and compare their results with liberals, conservatives, and libertarians.[12] He has changed his mind – he used to be more dismissive of the right, and conservative cultures – but he is still in the same bind as the rest of us, choosing the evidence to support his beliefs. [13] According to The Guardian review, Haidt says that we "tend to shape or select the evidence in order to justify our convictions." He uses the metaphor of a mahout or rider—our conscious intellect—on an elephant—our "gut instinct, trained by brute evolution"—that he is trying to nudge in a certain direction. Based on this survey, conservatives and republicans score higher on the five moral receptors on the side of "good order and individual responsibility towards the herd", while liberals and left wing parties score higher on caring and fairness but have a more narrow "range of moral impulses".[12] The Guardian also said that by 2012, Haidt had had "changed his mind – he used to be more dismissive of the right, and conservative cultures – but he is still in the same bind as the rest of us, choosing the evidence to support his beliefs."[12]

"If you think that moral reasoning is something we do to figure out the truth, you’ll be constantly frustrated by how foolish, biased, and illogical people become when they disagree with you. But if you think about moral reasoning as a skill we humans evolved to further our social agendas—to justify our own actions and to defend the teams we belong to—then things will make a lot more sense. Keep your eye on the intuitions, and don’t take people’s moral arguments at face value. They’re mostly post hoc constructions made up on the fly, crafted to advance one or more strategic objectives."

— Jonathan Haidt. The Righteous Mind.

In May of 2014, Greg Lukianoff, First Amendment attorney, had started working at Foundation for Individual Rights in Education (FIRE) as Director of Legal and Public Advocacy in 2001 and then served as President since 2007, shared concerns with Haidt about the shift in attitudes towards free speech. Prior to 2013, most of his work involved defending students against campus administrators, but in 2014 students began to request trigger warnings. In his 2012 book, Unlearning Liberty: Campus Censorship and the End of American Debate, Lukianoff examined how certainty can limit intellectual growth and impede freedom of speech. Inflexible certitude leaves no room for change or doubt and intellectual progress.[14]The belief in your own perfectly formed truth can lead to antipathy.Cite error: A <ref> tag is missing the closing </ref> (see the help page).


In their 2016 Organization Studies article by Dirk Lindebaum and Gabriel Yiannis distinguished between righteous anger, indignation, simple aggression and moral anger. They examined the "pro-social capabilities" of anger and endorsed Haidt's view that anger is underappreciated.[8] They used the definition of moral anger as an "aroused emotional state" that stemmed from a "primary appraisal of a moral standard violation" that "impacts others more than oneself", and "motivates corrective behaviour intended to improve the social condition, even in the face of significant personal risk" that was described by Lindebaum and Deanna Geddes in their 2015 article.[8]: 6 [15]

References[edit]

  1. ^ Aristotle. "Book II". Rhetoric. Translated by W. Rhys Roberts. 350 BC
  2. ^ Kemp, Simon; Strongman, K. T. (1995). "Anger Theory and Management: A Historical Analysis". The American Journal of Psychology. 108 (3): 397–417. doi:10.2307/1422897. ISSN 0002-9556. JSTOR 1422897. Retrieved 2019-09-01.
  3. ^ Kristjánsson, Kristján (2005). "Can We Teach Justified Anger?". Journal of Philosophy of Education. 39 (4): 671–689. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9752.2005.00463.x. ISSN 1467-9752. Retrieved 2019-09-01.
  4. ^ a b Leighton, Stephen (2002). "Aristotle's Account of Anger: Narcissism and Illusions of Self-Sufficiency". Ratio. 15 (1): 23–45. doi:10.1111/1467-9329.00174. ISSN 1467-9329. Retrieved 2019-09-01. This article was cited by 2. Aristotle, 1378/1991
  5. ^ Haidt, J.; Koller, S. H.; Dias, M. G. (October 1993). "Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat your dog?". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 65 (4): 613–628. doi:10.1037//0022-3514.65.4.613. ISSN 0022-3514. PMID 8229648. Cited by 1684.
  6. ^ a b c Haidt, Jonathan (2003). "The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment". In Davidson, R. J.; Scherer, K. R.; Goldsmith, H. H. (eds.). Handbook of affective sciences. Series in affective science. Vol. 108. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 814–834. ISSN 0033-295X.
  7. ^ a b Keltner, Dacher; Haidt, Jonathan (1999). "Social functions of emotions at four levels of analysis". Cognition and Emotion. 13 (5): 505–521. ISSN 1464-0600. SemanticScholar scores for this article: 537 Citations, 62 Highly Influenced Papers, 416 Cite Background, 17 Cite Methods, 14 Cite Results.
  8. ^ a b c d Lindebaum, Dirk; Geddes, Deanna (July 2016). "The place and role of (moral) anger in organizational behavior studies". Journal of Organizational Behavior. 37 (5): 738–757. doi:10.1002/job.2065. ISSN 0894-3796. PMC 5064625. PMID 27773966. Retrieved 2019-09-01.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: PMC format (link)
  9. ^ McHugh, Cillian; McGann, Marek; Igou, Eric R.; Kinsella, Elaine L. (2017-10-04). "Searching for Moral Dumbfounding: Identifying Measurable Indicators of Moral Dumbfounding". Collabra: Psychology. 3 (1): 23. doi:10.1525/collabra.79. ISSN 2474-7394. Retrieved 2019-09-01.
  10. ^ Haidt, Jonathan; Hersh, Matthew A. (2001). "Sexual morality: The cultures and emotions of conservatives and liberals". Journal of Applied Social Psychology. 31: 191–221.
  11. ^ Haidt, J. (October 2001). "The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment" (PDF). Psychological Review. 108 (4): 814–834. ISSN 0033-295X. PMID 11699120. Cited by 7,974.
  12. ^ a b c Lezard, Nicholas (2013-05-07). "The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion by Jonathan Haidt – review". The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. Retrieved 2019-09-01.
  13. ^ Haidt, Jonathan (2012). The Righteous Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Religion. ISBN 978-0307377906.
  14. ^ McGettigan, Timothy (2014-01-01). "Unlearning Liberty: Campus Censorship and the End of American Debate". Theory in Action. 7 (1): 85. ISSN 1937-0229. Retrieved 2019-09-01.
  15. ^ Lindebaum, Dirk; Gabriel, Yiannis (2016-07-01). "Anger and Organization Studies: From Social Disorder to Moral Order". Organization Studies. 37 (7): 903–918. doi:10.1177/0170840616640848. ISSN 0170-8406. Retrieved 2019-09-01.